Thursday 13 October 2016

BOOK REVIEW: Phantasmagorical Man




Susan Roland.  Hitler’s Art Thief: Hildebrand Gurlitt, the Nazis, and the Looting of Europe’s Treasures.  New York: St Martin’s Press, 2015.  xiv + 386 pp + 16 pp of unnumbered black-and-white and coloured plates.

Since the early 1990s, books and articles on Nazi art looting, plundering and confiscations from private Jewish collectors and public museums have proliferated, and these added to the innumerable courtroom documents and legal reports prepared by lawyers, co-opted scholars and bureaucrats to fight for and against cases of restitution make up an irrefutable argument for the extent of the crime, its significance to the history of the Holocaust, and, more and more, to the way in which the trade in stolen paintings provided much-needed cash to keep the Third Reich fighting at least two or three years beyond that its own industrial and financial base would have allowed.  How many millions of lives could have been saved had not the Swiss provided a means for using art sales to finance the purchase of vital materiel for the Wehrmacht and the Luftwaffe, let alone the construction of death camps and crematoria? Or what destruction could have been prevented throughout the battlefields and cities of Europe had not the greedy private and institutional dealers in North America circled the auction houses to feed off the vast amount of under-priced masterpieces that flooded into the market from the late 1930s through to the end of World War Two (and even beyond)?

Documentary and feature films, glamorous and gritty, as well as novels and television dramas, romantic and ridiculous, provide another dimension, the human tragedy of so many millions of lives ruined and so much art lost and the grotesque and even farcical scenes of perfidious buffoons stealing and cheating from one another.  Some of these materials deal with the victims, some with the  victimizers, and some with the inadvertent heroes or abetters of further grief and humiliation, naïve judges who have no sense of history, perplexed family members who are bamboozled into bad deals, ambitious lawyers blinded to the personal feelings they trample on, cynical politicians trying to hide their own or their parents’ collusion during the war, idealist scholars trudging on through the mud unaware of how far their own careers are being stunted…. 

Art was not just big business in the Third Reich run by wretched little creatures, it was what mattered, at a time when currencies around the world had suffered enormously during the Great Depression, often as philatelists know from a hyperinflation that made a letter across town cost several million marks or pengos, objets d’art substituted for other kinds of investment and savings, so that robbing Jewish families of their possessions was effectively destroying their lives.  Not just outright pilfering but also forced sales imposed on desperate people—some made to sign documents while already in a concentration camp—and huge taxes that had to be paid in order to cross borders, all this signalled a feeding frenzy among the unscrupulous dealers, auction houses, museum directors and individuals seeking bargains at the expense of other people’s misery.

And there they all are laid out before us in this book, from the bigwigs, like Hitler and Goering, who credited themselves with enormous knowledge and sensitivity as art connoisseurs, to the lesser beings who scurried about like rats and cockroaches, doing their duty, cheating on one another, trying to protect their personal collections and their families, willing to betray anyone and everyone and especially to see Jews and political dissidents be taken away to certain death, preparing complicated lies and half-truths to exonerate themselves when the inevitable end came to the Third Reich.

The whole enterprise of documenting this sad and ridiculous, horrible and pathetic series of events is far from over, not just because museum directors and legal experts still clash over unresolved cases in hundreds of unresolved cases—in the United States, as well as in Europe—as second and third generation heirs to murdered and plundered victims become aware of what had been done to their families and where long-lost or presumably destroyed objects of great financial as well as sentimental value emerge in auction catalogues and provenance records of respectable institutions, as well as in misattributed displays in scholarly tomes and much-touted travelling exhibitions.  Moreover, after the fall of the Soviet Union and the running out of time-limits on locked archives around the world, greater stores of documents, photographs and private memoirs become available to be sifted through. 

What Susan Roland does, for she is more novelist than historian, is extrapolate from the evidence the feelings, personality and thus the motivations of the family she focuses on, especially Cornelius the grandfather who was an architect historian, Hildebrand the father who as the title indicated was Hitler’s art thief (or “king Raffke”), and Cornelius Gurlitt the son who recently was discovered to be hoarding thousands of supposedly lost paintings in his Munich flat.  She synthesises many of the latest books on Nazi Art Looting, ferrets out details from the scholarly articles, legal documents and private memoirs now available and sets these facts within the contexts of political, military, diplomatic and artistic events and theories; but then, what fictional writers have always done in creating historical novels and romances, Roland imagines what the characters think, and feel, paints word-pictures of how they converse and dream, and creates the illusion of coherent understanding where professional historians are limited to probable scenarios, debatable missing links in the chain of cause-and-effect, and honest confessions of ignorance as to the meaning of it all. 


After the death of the elder Hildebrand in an automobile accident and soon after that of his mother by cancer, young Cornelius was left alone, and had only his married sister to relate to.  He eventually became, in Roland’s expression, a “phantasmagorical man”, perhaps autistic, certainly withdrawn, secretive, and cut off from most of the post-war and then even the digitally communicative world, but all in all no fool.  Living within the law, as he understood it, he kept to himself and “his friends”, the paintings his father had collected through means that for the most part Cornelius—who is presented as a somewhat pathetic figure of a child whose personality and mind was blighted by his parents’ greed—was unaware of, always maintaining to himself and others that Hildebrand had been a heroic saviour and protector of art from the Nazis.   After nearly seventy years of a rather furtive existence of selling one painting at a time for cash, he was finally caught put on suspicion of tax evasion, hounded by the police and the press, bewildered by the unwanted attention, grieved by the confiscation of his “friends,” and then, shortly before his death in his nineties, he made a will, leaving his whole collection to a small museum in Bern, Switzerland.  That museum agreed to accept all but contested works of art, and thus the matter stands, with few instances of restitution made, much gnashing of teeth by German officials, and most of the world not much the wiser as to the full extent of whereabouts all the hoard Hildebrand Gurlitt had amassed by one shady deal or nefarious transaction or another

Tuesday 11 October 2016

Misreading and Misunderstanding Literature, History & Philosophy



Here we Go Again

Reading Chaucer’s heart-rending portrait of a child
ritually murdered by Jews in The Pardoner’sTale….[1]

Oh really?  Has this author, who claims that he spent four years studying the “classics of English Literature” actually ever read Chaucer’s Canterbury Tales?  Go back to the text and look at what is there in the strange narrative recounted of how a little Christian scholar at a choir school somewhere in the East is killed, not by the Pardoner , but by the Prioress.  The boy, barely old enough to memorize the Latin hymns he is learning to chant, walks through the central street in a Jewish quarter of his city singing Alma Redemptoris (Mother of Mercy) in praise of the Virgin Mary.  Though this little clergeon has no idea of what the words mean, the people who hear it do, and one of them is enraged, pulls the child off to the side, stabs him and throws him in a privy.  One ordinary Jew, not the whole community or a cabal of rabbis; a crime of passion carried out in secret, not a ritual act.  There is no drawing of blood to make matzoh, no attempt to parody or repeat the Crucifixion.  

If there is anything religious in The Prioress’s Tale it is in her attempt to provide an occasion for a miracle by the Virgin Mary because the not-quite-yet-completely dead victim lying in the open sewer continues to sing his hymn.  When this is is heard, it is heard by Christian officials in the town who then call upon the Muslim rulers—for this is an Eastern place where Jews and Christians live by sufferance under Islamic rule.  The boy’s corpse is carried out of the Jewish quarter to the Christian neighbourhood and placed in a church.  Investigating the victim, the clergyman removes a piece of the Eucharistic wafer from the child’s mouth and the singing ceases. The Christian mob, with the tacit approval of the qadi or Islamic judge, race back to the  juderia or calle , grab a group of Jews, and kill them on a public pyre.

If you look closely at Chaucer’s text and see how he deliberately avoids all the specific markers of a Blood Libel narrative, you still have to wonder why he makes the Prioress—that rather foolish, snobbish and hypocritical woman who was once Lady Eglyntine before she was put into a convent as its head—tell such a bloodthirsty tale.  Not only do we know from her introductory description in The General Prologue to the Canterbury Tales that she  has no religious calling and still tries to maintain her courtly mannerisms, being more concerned with etiquette than faith or spirituality, and if she has any mercy in her soul, it is squeamishness about mice caught  a trap.  But we learn from her own Prologue to her Tale that she is obsessed by mouths and what goes in and out of them, and not only words.  In fact, a very close and symptomatic reading of the text indicates that she was probably abused as a child, if not by her father or brother, then by someone else who forced her to have oral sex; and her neurotic traits may be why she was taken off the marriage circuit and placed in a religious house where, too, her own sexual frustrations fester. 

Like those commentators who continue to read The Merchant of Venice as though it were a vicious slander against Jews, Shylock in particular, and castigate Shakespeare as an anti-Semite—as certainly T.S. Eliot and Ezra Pound later were—the author of this essay on Martin Heidegger undermines his own argument by such an obvious and egregious error.  Again a close reading of Shakespeare’s tragedy (or is it more a tragi-comedy?) can see that whatever Shylock’s faults, they are given motivation in his environment—a Venice which is ruled over by a love-sick neurotic Duke, under the thumb of a local Inquisition, and peopled by Christian hypocrites of various sorts, not least by young lovers who lack scruples, principles and refined feelings—thus will go against the stipulations of a will, falsify legal interpretations in court to win a case, and misconstrue the traditions of courtly love to seduce one another. 

As for Adam Kirsch ‘s evaluation of Martin Heidegger as a Nazi, he is certainly correct there. But not quite so when he tells us that Heidegger is nonetheless a preeminent twentieth-century philosopher, and that he still has trouble reconciling his very negative feelings about the man who joined the Nazi party and oversaw the dismissal of its Jewish professors and has never felt the need to apologize for his collaboration with the perpetrators of the Holocaust—and his admiration for Being and Time, Heidegger’s magnum opus.  Perhaps the “refreshment” of old ideas that Kirsch finds so important in this philosopher’s work need to be reconsidered in the light who are the actual followers of Heidegger in the Post-Modernist pantheon of writers (one hesitates to say “thinkers”), beginning with Hannah Arendt, the German philosopher’s student mistress.  As Stephen  Hicks puts it:


Heidegger is notorious for the obscurity of his prose and for his actions and inactions on behalf of the National Socialists during the 1930s, and he is unquestionably the leading twentieth-century philosopher for the postmodernists. Derrida and Foucault identify themselves as followers of Heidegger.[2]

These people started a movement which these days push for the anti-Israeli measures, make excuses for terrorism and anti-Americanism, and generate further ideas inimical to the essential Jewish ideas of truth, justice and mutual responsibility.  Kirsch rightly points out that the recently published and translated Black Books of Heidegger leave no doubt that he was an out-and-out anti-Semite, tended towards and often coincided with Nazi principles, and blamed the Jews for any misunderstandings of his work.  The conclusion Kirsch reaches then?

Heidegger’s Nazism does not mean we should stop thinking about him: on the contrary, it is all the more urgent to think about him so we that we can learn how to think against him.

Is that it?  Learning to think against him, not doing anything at all to counter the pernicious influence he had and still has on so many of the so-called great great thinkers in the universities and media today?  With misunderstandings of Chaucer’s tale and Shakespeare’s play constantly recurring in terms that call for them not to be taught any more or produced on the public stage, resistance to repeated explanations of how the poem and the tragedy are about rather than for Judeophobic themes and images that run through most of our own high culture—and therefore ought to be topics for discussion in classes and newspapers so as to teach how great writers oppose pernicious  ideas—why does Heidegger get away with it?  Of course, I am not arguing for censorship but for cogent, incisive and sensitive readings of all texts which have great influence on the world we live in.  If Chaucer and Shakespeare should be taught and produced in terms of their real meanings, and that includes how generations have misunderstood them and misused them, why should Heidegger be allowed to stand as an unquestioned major source of contemporary thought and not be revealed through his disciples and avatars and thus downgraded to the dangerous background?[3] 




[1] Adam Kirsch, “Heidegger was really a Nazi” The Tablet (26 September 2016).
[2] http://www.stephenhicks.org/2009/11/30/heidegger-and-postmodernism-ep/
[3] A convenient list of who these pleasant folk are can be found in Giulio Meotti, “Meet the Western Charlatans Justifying Jihad” Gatestone Institutre (28 September 2016) online at https://www.gatestoneinstitute.org/8741/western-intellectuals-jihad; they include Michel Orfray, Thomas Piketty, Peter Sloterdijk, Jürgen Habermas, Slavoj Zisek, José Saramago, Jean Baudrillard, Karlheinz Stockhausen, Dario Fo…